|
greek philosophy
Aristotle defines elements to be composed of properties
that can be felt by touching. He uses two pairs of opposites,
hot-cold and wet-dry, to define four elements, which he
names fire, earth, water and air. And he identifies wet-dry
with soft-hard, viscous-brittle and smooth-rough. Unlike
later commonly the case, he does not consistently identify
hot-cold with active-passive and light-heavy. If you do, you
get a one-to-one correspondence to my previous definition
of the elements in terms of in/out and rest/move:
🜂 |
fire |
hot (active) |
dry (hard) |
emo |
🜃 |
earth |
cold (passive) |
dry (hard) |
ero |
🜄 |
water |
cold (passive) |
wet (soft) |
emi |
🜁 |
air |
hot (active) |
wet (soft) |
eri |
Aristotle defines a fifth element as immutable, moving
only in circles and existing only in space, while the other
four elements move linearly. And he also arranges the four
elements essentially in a circle in which they transform into
each other by flipping one of hot↔cold or wet↔dry at
each transition, while not completely excluding transitions
that flip both at the same time, but considering them more
difficult and slower. The shared theme of a circle links the
transformation of elements to the fifth element.
[image]
In other words, the same circle as tentatively derived
earlier on from my definition of the elements, and a similar
meaning related to e5, as also derived earlier.
Passive is inertial in a sense: Outside ero resists more
to get into motion than emo resists to get to rest; inside
emi resists more to get to rest than eri resists to get into
motion. In rough equivalence to inertial and gravitational
mass in physics, inert (passive) would be heavy and dense,
swift (active) would be light and thin.
leads
-
Aristotle. On Generation and Corruption. Around 350 BCE.
-
“Since, then, we are looking for ‘originative sources’ of
perceptible body; and since ‘perceptible’ is equivalent to ‘tangible’,
and ‘tangible’ is that of which the perception is touch;
it is clear that not all the contrarieties constitute ‘forms’ and
‘originative sources’ of body, but only those which correspond
to touch.” (Book II, translated by H. Joachim)
-
“From moist and dry are derived (iii) the fine and coarse,
viscous and brittle, hard and soft, and the remaining tangible
differences. For (a) since the moist has no determinate shape,
but is readily adaptable and follows the outline of that which
is in contact with it, it is characteristic of it to be ‘such as
to fill up’. Now ‘the fine’ is ‘such as to fill up’. For ‘the fine’
consists of subtle particles; but that which consists of small
particles is ‘such as to fill up’, inasmuch as it is in contact
whole with whole–and ‘the fine’ exhibits this character in a
superlative degree. Hence it is evident that the fine derives
from the moist, while the coarse derives from the dry. Again
(b) ‘the viscous’ derives from the moist: for ‘the viscous’
(e.g. oil) is a ‘moist’ modified in a certain way. ‘The brittle’,
on the other hand, derives from the dry: for ‘brittle’ is that
which is completely dry–so completely, that its solidification
has actually been due to failure of moisture. Further (c) ‘the
soft’ derives from the moist. For ‘soft’ is that which yields
to pressure by retiring into itself, though it does not yield
by total displacement as the moist does–which explains why
the moist is not ‘soft’, although ‘the soft’ derives from the
moist. ‘The hard’, on the other hand, derives from the dry: for
‘hard’ is that which is solidified, and the solidified is dry.”
-
“The elementary qualities are four […]. Hence it is evident
that the ‘couplings’ of the elementary qualities will be four:
hot with dry and moist with hot, and again cold with dry and
cold with moist. […] Fire is hot and dry, whereas Air is hot
and moist (Air being a sort of aqueous vapour); and Water
is cold and moist, while Earth is cold and dry.”
-
Aristotle arranges the elements in a cycle fire-air-water-earth:
“Thus (i) the process of conversion will be quick between
those which have interchangeable ‘complementary factors’,
but slow between those which have none. The reason is that
it is easier for a single thing to change than for many. Air, e.g.
will result from Fire if a single quality changes: for Fire, as we
saw, is hot and dry while Air is hot and moist, so that there
will be Air if the dry be overcome by the moist. Again, Water
will result from Air if the hot be overcome by the cold: for Air,
as we saw, is hot and moist while Water is cold and moist,
so that, if the hot changes, there will be Water. So too, in
the same manner, Earth will result from Water and Fire from
Earth, since the two ‘elements’ in both these couples have
interchangeable ‘complementary factors’. For Water is moist
and cold while Earth is cold and dry–so that, if the moist
be overcome, there will be Earth: and again, since Fire is
dry and hot while Earth is cold and dry, Fire will result from
Earth if the cold pass-away. […] (ii) the transformation of
Fire into Water and of Air into Earth, and again of Water and
Earth into Fire and Air respectively, though possible, is more
difficult because it involves the change of more qualities.”
-
In On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle considers
light-heavy not to be an attribute of any specific elements:
“(i) heavy and light are neither active nor susceptible. Things
are not called ‘heavy’ and ‘light’ because they act upon, or
suffer action from, other things. But the ‘elements’ must be
reciprocally active and susceptible, since they ‘combine’ and
are transformed into one another. On the other hand (ii) hot
and cold, and dry and moist, are terms, of which the first pair
implies power to act and the second pair susceptibility.”
But in On the Heavens, he considers air and fire as light and
water and earth as heavy, in the order earth-water-air-fire, and
postulates the existence of an immutable fifth element that
dominates in the sky, is neither light nor heavy and moves in
circles, while the first four elements move linearly:
“[…] all locomotion, as we term it, is either straight or
circular or a combination of these two, which are the only simple
movements. […] Now revolution about the centre is circular
motion, while the upward and downward movements are in a
straight line, ‘upward’ meaning motion away from the centre,
and ‘downward’ motion towards it. […] For if the natural
motion is upward, it will be fire or air, and if downward, water
or earth. […] circular motion is necessarily primary. For the
perfect is naturally prior to the imperfect, and the circle is a
perfect thing. […] These premises clearly give the conclusion
that there is in nature some bodily substance other than
the formations we know, prior to them all and more divine
than they. […] there is something beyond the bodies that
are about us on this earth, different and separate from them;
and that the superior glory of its nature is proportionate to its
distance from this world of ours. […] things are heavy and
light relatively to one another; air, for instance, is light relatively
to water, and water light relatively to earth. The body,
then, which moves in a circle cannot possibly possess either
heaviness or lightness. For neither naturally nor unnaturally
can it move either towards or away from the centre. […] this
body will be ungenerated and indestructible and exempt from
increase and alteration […] earth is enclosed by water, water
by air, air by fire, and these similarly by the upper bodies.”
(Book I, translated by J. Stocks)
-
Aristotle appears to consistently consider the pair of opposites
hot/cold active and the pair wet/dry passive, see the quote
from On Generation and Corruption above, or the following
quote from Meteorology:
“All this makes it clear that bodies are formed by heat and
cold and that these agents operate by thickening and solidifying.
It is because these qualities fashion bodies that we
find heat in all of them, and in some cold in so far as heat is
absent. These qualities, then, are present as active, and the
moist and the dry as passive, and consequently all four are
found in mixed bodies.” (Book IV, translated by E. Webster)
-
In the outside world, the elements water and air (essentially
liquids and gases or gas-like phenomena like clouds or smoke)
appear softer and more fluidly in motion than the element
earth (solid matter). The element fire (flames, lightning),
however, does not appear to be visibly hard, while, like earth,
quite closely related to dryness.
-
While many works of Aristotle and Plato have been preserved
in their entirety, works of earlier philosophers, as well of many
later ones, like the Stoics, have usually only survived as
fragmentary quotes by later philosophers, typically around early
CE or even later. Since this was also the time in which the
“canonical view” on the elements emerged for centuries to
follow in astrology, alchemy, medicine, etc., it is difficult to
reconstruct other views with certainty. Moreover, it seems
that some schools of philosophy might have had oaths which
would bind their members not to speak about certain
fundamental views, or only in carefully veiled form.
In a nutshell, the earliest source I know of that attributes fire
and air to active, and water and earth to passive is Cicero
in Academica (45 BCE), possibly influenced by the Stoics.
The first attribution of the same elements to male-female in
astrology is Vettius Valens in Anthologia (2nd century CE).
Aristotle names Empedocles at least twice as the first to have
considered four elements. Plato introduces a fifth element in
the Timaeus, most likely predating Aristotle.
A fragmentary closer look below and in following sections.
-
David Sedley writes in chapter 11 of The Cambridge History
of Hellenistic Philosophy (2000) that the Stoic’s identification
of fire and air with active emerged from medical tradition,
from pneuma, breath, which was seen as a mixture of fire and
air, and mentions also that this identification was originally
not exclusively the only view of the Stoics in their time.
-
In Academica (45 BCE), Cicero lets Antiochus of Ascalon say
the following, influenced by Aristotle and maybe the Stoics:
“Accordingly air […] and fire and water and earth are primary;
while their derivatives are the species of living creatures
and of the things that grow out of the earth. Therefore those
things are termed […] elements; and among them air and
fire have motive and efficient force, and the remaining divisions
[…] water and earth, receptive and ‘passive’ capacity.
Aristotle deemed that there existed a certain fifth sort of
element, in a class by itself and unlike the four that I have
mentioned above, which was the source of the stars and of
thinking minds.” (Book I 26, translated by H. Rackham)
-
A bit later astrological views emerged that see fire and air as
male, and water and earth as female. See Vettius Valens’s
Anthologia in the 2nd century CE and hints in earlier texts by
Dorotheus of Sidon and Marcus Manilius. These views have
essentially prevailed, including in medieval alchemy and up to
contemporary astrology.
-
In contemporary astrology, the element fire is associated with
(visual) imagination and impulse, air with (abstract) thinking
and communication, water with feelings and faith, earth with
pragmatic realism—to give just a rough summary.
-
Most things in the sky beyond clouds are round or cyclic: sun
and moon are round; planets, as well as stars during night
and seasons, move periodically in predictable cycles.
-
The fifth element is also called ether or aether and quintessence.
Many different views of the fifth element and closely
related concepts have emerged over time.
Plato used the word aether to describe the purest form of air
in the Timaeus. But there is also a strong association of the
sky with fire, because stars and planets appear to emit light
and the sun provides heat, and also because fire was often
considered the lightest of the four elements.
The fifth element is generally considered “divine” because
gods were often believed to live in heaven. And it is often
also seen as special in other ways, like able to create life, or
immortal like the soul or maybe pneuma, or able to create
matter and to hold it together, or maybe identified by some
alchemists with the philosopher’s stone, which was believed
to be able to transform matter, like lead to gold, etc. ?
-
Do such associations (historically founded or not) fit well with
the definition of e5 simply because they all keep going in circles
around the same questions ?
-
Apuleius in The Doctrines of Plato in the 2nd century CE:
“In the first place, the twin pupils of the eyes are very clear,
and, shining with a certain light of vision, they possess the
office of knowing light; while hearing, by partaking of the
nature of air, has a perception of sounds, through messengers
in the air; whereas the taste, being a sense more relaxed, is
on that account suited to things rather moist and watery;
but the touch, as being of the earth and corporeal, perceives
things, that are rather solid, and which can be handled and
struck against. Of those things likewise, which are changed,
when corrupted there is a separate perception. For in the
middle of the region of the face Nature has placed the nostrils,
by the double door-way of which there passes an odour
together with the breath; and that conversions and changes
furnish the causes of smelling; and that they are perceived
from substances, when corrupted or burnt, or in a mucous
or moistened state; […].” (Book I, 14, translated by G. Burges)
Even though most of what he writes is from Platos’ Timaeus,
it seems that a view of see-fire, hear-air, taste-water, touch-earth
is something that Apuleius implicitly added. Even more
so with the implicit association of transformations of the
elements with smell and the 5th element, which would maybe
already mirror the definition of e5 in my model…
-
According to Diogenes Laërtius in the third century CE, the
Stoics would have identified fire with hot, earth with dry,
water with wet, and air with cold (and dry):
“[…] the four elements are all equally an essence without any
distinctive quality, namely, matter; but fire is the hot, water
the moist, air the cold, and earth the dry—though this last
quality is also common to the air. The fire is the highest,
and that is called aether, in which first of all the sphere was
generated in which the fixed stars are set, then that in which
the planets revolve; after that the air, then the water; and
the sediment as it were of all is the earth, which is placed in
the centre of the rest.” (7. LXIX, translated by C. Yonge)
The papyrus Anonymus Londinensis from about the first
century CE says essentially the same about Philistion (apparently
Philistion of Locri, a contemporary of Plato):
“Philiston thinks that we are composed of four ‘forms’, that
is, of four elements—fire, air, water, earth. Each of these too
has its own power; of fire the power is the hot, of air it is
the cold, of water the moist, and of earth the dry.” (XX 24,
translated by W. Jones)
According to David Hahm in The Origins of Stoic Cosmology
(1977), this view might have already been quite common
among physicians in classical times. Artistotle’s texts about
biology seem to implicitly reflect that view, like that air is
inhaled cold and exhaled hot (pneuma). Although there
appear to be no contemporary sources that would directly prove
such an identification, Hahm’s detailed argumentation that
the Stoics aimed for a unified view of the elements (unlike
apparently Aristotle) across all fields seems plausible.
In Stoic belief, the cosmos emerged from fire via air to water
to earth, and back (see Hahm for details), essentially along
Aristotle’s circle of the elements or light to heavy and back.
-
In ancient Greek philosophy there was also the idea of matter
consisting of indivisible physical units (atoms). In Plato’s
Timaeus, a model is presented that combines both views by
associating the elements with the five Platonic solids:
fire-tetrahedron, air-octahedron, water-icosahedron, earth-cube
and the “roundest” one, the dodecahedron, for the whole
world/universe (pan). Kepler’s drawings (1619):
[image]
Today they are usually paired cube-octahedron, dodecahedron-icosahedron
and tetrahedron-itself, because the centers of the
surfaces yield the corners of the dual body.
In 4 dimensions there are 6 generalized Platonic solids, in 5
and more dimensions always only 3, namely generalizations
of tetrahedron, cube and octahedron.
|